Descartes' Dream: Where Modernism Began --- As if It Mattered!
Descartes' Dream: From Sense to Nonsense
It is not surprising that
the philosophical-theological error that we refer to as "modernism"
should begin with a dream. The dream, or actually a set of three consecutive dreams,
happened on the night of November 10, 1619, the vigil of the Feast of St.
Martin of Tours, which was a time of great feasting in the France of Rene
Descartes's time. We are right to wonder whether Descartes "protests too
much," when he asserted in his autobiographical work that he had abstained
from wine for some time before the night of his famous dreams. What he does
admit, however, is that for several days prior to his experience, which would
transform the basic orientation of philosophy, he had felt a "steady rise
of temperature in his head."1
The young Descartes, some
23 years old when he found himself on that cold November's night "shut up
alone in a stove-heated room (poêle)" had been quite an
eccentric in his early years. Indeed, there appears to be some controversy
amongst English-speaking commentators as to whether poêle indicates that
Descartes was "shut up in a stove-heated room" or that he was
"shut up in a stove."2 Descartes's general
restlessness of spirit (not surprising if he were in the habit of shutting
himself up in stoves!) had manifested itself during his adolescent years when
he left behind his Jesuit schooling, of which he had a decidedly mixed
impression, and "took up the book of the world." Tired of what he
felt to be the endless intellectual discussions and controversies that taxed
and left dubious the minds of so many, he put aside the reading of books and
took up the practical matter of war, which the Central Europe of the early
seventeenth century had made available to him in the form of the Thirty Years
War between the forces of the Habsburg Catholic Holy Roman Emperor and those of
the Protestant Princes of Northern Europe. It was as a "fighting man"
of the army of the Duke of Bavaria (even though there is no real historical evidence
that Descartes himself did any actual fighting) that he found himself on that
November day, holed up in a stove-heated room, wintering with the army in the
German city of Ulm. On this particular day, Descartes was meditating on the
"disunity and uncertainty" of his knowledge. Since his days at the
Jesuit lycée [i.e., high-school/college] at La Flèche, he had
marveled at mathematics, especially geometry, a science in which he found
certainty, necessity, and precision.3 How could he find a
basis for all knowledge so that it might have the same unity and certainty as
mathematics? Having in mind, for a number of years, a project and method to bring
all the sciences together within the context of a new universal philosophical
"wisdom," Descartes interpreted the vivid dreams that he had on the
night of the Vigil of the Feast of St. Martin as a sign from God Himself. From
that moment on, Descartes would believe that he had a divine mandate to
establish an all-encompassing science of human wisdom. He himself was so
convinced of this divine endorsement of his "mission," that he would
make a pilgrimage to the Holy House of Loreto in thanksgiving for this
"favor."4
What could be the content
of dreams that incited such a fervid sense of mission; a "mission"
taken so seriously that Descartes was ready to treat all systems of thought
developed prior to his own, especially that of Scholasticism, as
"pre-philosophical."5
Of these three dreams, it
is the third that best expresses the original thought and intention of Rene
Descartes's rationalism. During the dream that William Temple aptly refers to
as, "the most disastrous moment in the history of Europe," Descartes
saw before him two books. One was a dictionary, which appeared to him to be of
little interest and use. The other was a compendium of poetry entitled Corpus
Poetarum in which there appeared to be a union of philosophy with wisdom.
Moreover, the way in which Descartes interpreted this dream set the stage for
the rest of his life-long philosophical endeavors. For Descartes, the
dictionary stood merely for the sciences gathered together in their sterile and
dry disconnection; the collection of poems marked more particularly and
expressly the union of philosophy with wisdom. He indicates that one should not
be astonished that poets abound in utterances more weighty, more full of
meaning and better expressed, than those found in the writings of philosophers.
In utterances which appear odd when coming from a man who would go down in
history as the father of Rationalism, Descartes ascribes the "marvel"
of the wisdom of the poets to the divine nature of inspiration and to the might
of phantasy, which "strikes out" the seeds of wisdom (existing in
the minds of all men like the sparks of fire in flints) far more easily and
directly than does reason in the philosophers. The writings of the professional
philosophers of his time struck Descartes as failing to supply that certitude,
human urgency, and attractive presentation which we associate with a wise
vision capable of organizing our knowledge and influencing our conduct.6
Math, Method, and Madness
It would be an
unfortunate intellectual and historical mistake to take Rene Descartes for a
relativist, who wished to undermine all certainty, along with dividing the
individual sciences from each other into airtight compartments. That the
contemporary end result of Cartesian Rationalism has been nothing but
relativism and the fragmentation of knowledge is, simply, the ironic outcome of
Descartes's efforts towards the attainment of certainty and a "universal
mathematics." Here we must remember the traditional Aristotelian/Thomistic
understanding that each specific science (e.g., botany and entomology)
had not only its own proper object of study (e.g., plants or insects),
but, also, its own proper method of investigation and demonstration. This
is why Descartes's insistence upon a single "universal" method,
resembling the method employed in geometry, is so destructive and disorienting.
As we shall see when we consider the method that Descartes constructs in order
to achieve scientific certainty, it was his departure from agreed upon
philosophical principles and fundamental presuppositions that causes the
philosophical trend he initiates to steer the post-Christian mind into the
ditch of democratic relativism and religious indifferentism.
To clear up
misconceptions about the thought of Rene Descartes, we need first emphasize
that even though Mathematics, especially the mathematical science of Geometry,
was going to provide for Descartes the general structure and procedure of his
intellectual method, it must be remembered that Descartes did not at all view
Mathematics as the highest and most intellectually efficacious science. Rather,
he took from Mathematics its "method," which he defines as
"reliable rules which are easy to apply, and such that if one follows them
exactly, one will never take what is false to be true or fruitlessly expend
one's mental efforts, but will gradually and constantly increase one's
knowledge (scientia) till one arrives at a true understanding within
one's capacity."7 What disturbed
Descartes about his own intellectual milieu was that men of learning were becoming
specialists to the extent that they were forgetting about achieving the state
of "wisdom," which had traditionally been the objective of both
philosopher and sage.
The image that Descartes
used to portray his understanding of the new rationalist scientific
"wisdom," was a tree, the "tree of wisdom." Every tree has
three aspects, roots from which the tree is fixed to the ground and from which
it gains its nourishment, the trunk of the tree which constitutes the main
quantitative mass of the tree and upholds the branches, and, finally, the
branches which produce the flower or the fruit which both perpetuate the tree's
existence and express the highest productive capabilities of the tree; so too
with the tree of philosophical and scientific knowledge. Descartes identifies
the roots of the tree with metaphysics, especially the three most
fundamental metaphysical concepts of God, the human thinking self, and the
external material world. These three ideas (N.B., already we can see the
inevitable movement of Rationalism and all the philosophical schools that are
related to it. The most fundamental realities in existence are
spoken of and philosophically treated as ideas rather than things), provide
the intellectual justification for the "trunk" of the tree, a
philosophically grounded physics that would give an account of all
motions of quantitative being. The three branches, which Descartes
speaks of, are the practical sciences of ethics, mechanics, and
medicine. These three were the sciences which Descartes felt had to be
necessarily grounded in metaphysical knowledge, which would allow mankind to
attain the goal that Descartes stated to be the primary goal of his new
scientific method, making mankind the "master of nature." It is very
interesting here to see that, from the perspective of the perennial
philosophical tradition, Descartes has inverted the very orientation of
pedagogy and scientific speculation. In a very real way, Descartes's tree is
"upside down." The practical arts and sciences should serve as the
practical "ground" (i.e., in the sense of providing for the
necessary ordering of the physical and social realm of man) for the ultimate
act of human intelligence, that of intellectual contemplation of nature, the
human soul, and most especially God. In Descartes's "Tree of Wisdom,"
the newly characterized "ideas" of God, the human "self,"
and the external material world are only the intellectually efficacious
principles, which allow for the deduction of an entire system of truths derived
from an analysis of the conceptual necessities inherent in the
"ideas" of God, the human thinking self, and the external material
world themselves.8In other words, what
ought to be the highest objects of intellectual contemplation–the goal and
fruit of all scientific speculation–become no more than a necessary
intellectual step in a logical method that has as its intent the subjection of
nature to the natural wishes and desires of man. It is interesting to note that
Descartes had as one of his greatest hopes for his new rationalist science, the
indefinite extension of human longevity. That Descartes himself should have
died at the relatively young age of 54, after a short spell of cold weather in
Stockholm, Sweden in 1650, foreshadowed the sterility of rationalist
"first principles" both in the speculative and in the practical
domains.
What is initially
difficult to fathom is how a system can be given the name
"rationalism" and, yet, appear prima facie to be so
counter-intuitive and irrational. Descartes's honest hope to derive all
scientific knowledge concerning the structure and motions of the universe in a
deductive way from three "self-evident" ideas by simply analyzing the
conceptual necessities inherent in those ideas appears not only supremely
irrational, but also downright fanciful. It is not surprising that the young
scientist Huygens, who was both a physicist and an astronomer, along with being
a contemporary of Descartes, saw nothing more in Descartes's great
"scientific" work Principes de la philosophie than an
extraordinarily interesting novel? What is even more irrational and
counter-intuitive is that Descartes understood it to be necessary to derive
this literal "universe" of scientific knowledge from the idea that
Descartes had of himself as an existing and thinking being. By having as the
foundation of one's science one's own mind and by determining that the mind
itself, by conceiving its own ideas "clearly and distinctly," could
judge whether the ideas that came to it were certain and true, the Rationalists
of the 17th and 18th centuries upheld a teaching on human intellectual autonomy
that was both absolute and without the slightest basis in normal human
experience. Moreover, one significant consequence of such a view of human
knowledge was the rejection of all appeals to authority, both philosophical and
dogmatic, in establishing intellectual certainty. Another part of the fall out
of the Rationalist attack on the Thomistic synthesis of theological and
philosophical learning, was the relegation of Theology, since it could not be
derived from the idea of the thinking self, to the realm of
"catechism," which was upheld solely on the basis of faith. Thus,
Cartesian Rationalism would relegate the believing man to a position of fideism
(i.e., an act of blind faith, unsupported or unsupportable by rational
proof or argument).
Intuition and Deduction
In order to derive these
foundational "first notions" (i.e., of God, the thinking self,
and the external material world) from which all the rest of human knowledge and
science would be derived in an a priori fashion (i.e., prior to
and exclusive of any sensible experience of the external natural world), the
mind, according the Cartesian Method, needed to engage in two distinct
processes. The first was analysis and the second was synthesis. Analysis
involved "dividing] up each of the difficulties which I was to examine
into as many parts as possible and as seemed requisite." Descartes was
convinced that he had followed this way of "analysis" (really, what
should be called reductionism) in his most influential book, The
Meditations on First Philosophy, by resolving the bounteous data of human
knowledge and experience into the primary existential proposition, Cogito,
ergo sum (i.e., I think, therefore, I am). According to Descartes, all
mental content could be reduced to three "innate" (i.e., meaning
"in born," that is, not gained by experience of the external world
known through the senses) ideas, the idea which I have of myself, the idea I
have of God, and the idea I have of materiality. These ideas were to be grasped
with an absolute and certain intuition. By "intuition,"
Descartes meant a purely intellectual activity, an intellectual
"seeing" or "vision," which is so clear and distinct that
it leaves no room for doubt.10 In another definition
of intuition, Descartes said, "Intuition is the conception, without doubt,
of an unclouded and attentive mind, which springs from the light of reason
alone."11 It was from these
primary and "irreducible" ideas, that Cartesian Rationalism believed
it could derive, through the intellectual process of deduction, all the
content of human science and wisdom. That such an a priori (i.e., that
which is gained prior to and independent of concrete, sensible experience of
the material world) conception of human science could ever pass itself off as
"rationalism," is one of the many ironies present in the history of
philosophy. Surely such counter-intuitive gibber can only be explained by the
Cartesian desire to establish the mind's reasoning process on the
foundation of the mind itself, rather than on a rational and lived encounter
with a material created order that the mind necessarily recognizes to exist
independently of the thinking "self."
The Cogito and
Philosophical Modernism
Several years have now
passed since I realized how numerous were the false opinions that in my youth I
had taken to be true, and thus how doubtful were all those that I had
subsequently built upon them. And thus I realized that once in my life I had to
raze everything to the ground and begin again from the original foundations, if
I wanted to establish anything firm and lasting in the sciences.12
With these words,
Descartes opens his Meditations, which will be the text destined to
create a revolution in the science of philosophy, providing to those who follow
this revolution an entirely new orientation and object of philosophical study.
As we see by the quotation above, it was Descartes's intention to
"raze" the edifice of his previously held opinions and build upon
these discredited ruins a new structure that would be able to stand the test of
every doubt that the Skeptics could throw at it.13
It is the key to understanding
Descartes, however, that we realize that he commenced his method to eliminate
doubt by appealing to doubt. This Cartesian technique of employing doubt
to achieve an overcoming of doubt and a putative certainty can be referred to
as a methodological doubt (i.e., it is a doubt employed so that all
doubt can be overcome). The most important thing to notice here is that
Descartes begins his philosophical reflection with doubt, rather than
the wonder at the order of material creation that characterizes
Aristotelian/Thomistic philosophy. Since Descartes realized that he could not
analyze, in any reasonable amount of time, all of his opinions that he
had newfound doubts about, he writes that, "Nor therefore need I survey
each opinion individually, a task that would be endless. Rather, because undermining
the foundations will cause whatever has been built upon them to crumble of its
own accord, I will attack those principles that supported everything I once
believed."14 What the kamikaze
crafts of Cartesian Doubt and Rationalism hit were the "twin towers"
of the Aristotelian philosophical system, 1) our trust
that the ideas in our minds are simply perfect reflections of the perceived
object in the natural world, and 2) the understanding that
the five senses provide us with a real and exact knowledge of the natures of
things in the material world. These two attacks were definitely part of a
philosophical jihad on Aristotle and his explanation of nature and the
human mind and person. To forget this overarching anti-Aristotelian aim would
be to overlook the heart of the matter. In this regard, we must say that
Descartes himself was more anti-Aristotelian than anti-Thomistic, since he
admitted, near the end of his life, that he had never read St. Thomas's Summa
Theologiae and even regretted the fact. What he knew about St. Thomas was,
therefore, received second hand from his scholastic manuals and his Jesuit
teachers.
Descartes tell us that it
is the information supplied to us by sensation that is the primary
object of attack in his attempt to "strike at the foundations" of his
former opinions. It was his "uncertainty" about the reliability of
the data of sensation and of the images in the imagination, which have their
origin in the sensible species coming from sensation, that provoked him to
state the following: "Surely whatever I had admitted until now as most
true I received either from the senses or through the senses. However, I have
noticed that the senses are sometimes deceptive; and it is a mark of prudence
never to place our complete trust in those who have deceived us even
once."15Following up on the
observation that was made at the beginning of this article, that much of
Descartes's philosophical analysis is related, by Descartes himself, to the
phenomenon of dreaming. At the end of Meditation 6, Descartes states that it
was the continual misjudgments that the mind made while "in" a
dream-state, that most undermined his trust in his sensible experience of the
world around him. In Meditation 1, Descartes states that his normal trust in
the veracity of his mental experience of the sensible world was all "well
and good," "were I not a man who is accustomed to sleeping at night,
and to experiencing in my dreams the very same things, or now and then even
less plausible ones, as these insane people do when they are awake."16
By inserting this slight
doubt concerning the veracity of his sensible and imaginative experience,
Descartes moved to the next stage of his method that was to state that, "I
should withhold my assent no less from opinions that are not completely
certain and indubitable than I would from those that are patently false. For
this reason, it will suffice for the rejection of all these opinions, if I find
in each one some reason for doubt." Therefore, for the sake of a method
that is supposed to yield only certain knowledge, Descartes is going to reject
as deceptive and distortive all his ideas that have their origin in sensation.
Descartes's
mathematician's jihad against the probable will even turn itself upon
the science of mathematics, when, in his attempt to radicalize his
methodological doubt, Descartes will postulate the idea of an evil genius. This
"evil genius" is used as a conceptual device to undermine our trust
in the certainty of our judgments concerning mathematical truths. That 4+4=8
seems perfectly evident, with no serious reason for doubt. However, what if a
being had created me who desired to deceive me and he made me in such a way
that everything that I take to be absolutely certain is actually false. With
this idea of a creative "evil genius," Descartes clears the mental
field of all certainty that could upstage his autonomous thinking self.
It is in Meditation 2,
where Descartes initiates the long lasting trend which we could name
"philosophical modernism" or subjectivism, which bears its bitter
fruit in the New Theology in the 20th century. It is here where we see the
fatal "movement towards the thinking self," which characterizes most
all of the philosophical movements in the last 350 years. It is, no doubt,
fitting that Descartes use this counterÂintuitive idea of the "evil
creative genius" to finally achieve his one absolutely certain truth, the
truth that his own thinking mind exists, precisely at the moment that he is
thinking the idea "I exist." Descartes, referring to the
methodological device of the "evil genius," states, "there is some
deceiver or other who is supremely powerful and supremely sly and who is always
deliberately deceiving me. Then too there is no doubt that that I exist,
if he is deceiving me. And let him do his best at deception, he will
never bring it about that I am nothing so long as I shall think that I am
something."17 Descartes must
exist, since even if there were such a thing as an "evil genius" who
is perpetually deceiving him, still he must exist in order to be deceived. The
very fact of his possible complete deception is proof for the certain existence
of the thinking self. Descartes has found his first certainty; he has
established a new foundation for philosophy. For all those who follow in his
wake, philosophy will have as its grounding human consciousness, and it will
have as its subject matter the ideas present in the human mind.
Descartes, however,
whatever the ultimate philosophical consequences of his ideas, did not want to
fall into a position of solipsism (i.e., the philosophical position
which states that the only thing which one can know are the ideas in one's own
mind). But, in order to avoid this imprisoning subjectivism, Descartes needed
to establish for certain that there existed a being that had its existence
independently of Descartes's own thinking self. He also needed to discover an
"idea," not subject to doubt, which would be conceptually rich enough
to yield an entire physics of the material world. Descartes knew that the idea
that he had of himself as a thinking and willing self was not enough. The only
reality that could fit the bill was God Himself, an infinite, perfect, and
all-powerful being. However, a God which is merely an idea would not yield such
results. Descartes's task in Meditation 3, will be to prove, on the fact that
Descartes has an idea of God in his mind, that such a God truly exists as an
infinite, perfect, and all-powerful being. Even though, in doing this,
Descartes uses an ostensibly old argument called the "ontological
argument," nevertheless, the use of such an argument is going to have
profound effects on modern philosophy and theology's position on the origin of
the idea of God.
The Self and the Idea of
God
Descartes's proof for the
real existence of God, being restricted by his method to analyzing his own
ideas and not the created natural world around him, is that since he had an
idea of a God who was an infinite and perfect being, that God must truly exist,
since he, as a limited and imperfect thinking self, could not be the origin of
the idea of a unlimited and perfect being. A really existing God, who is
unlimited and perfect, must then have imprinted in Descartes's mind the idea of
Himself. Therefore, God must truly exist, and He must exist independently of
Descartes's thinking self.
Having secured the real
existence of God, Descartes then uses the perfection of God to infer his
veracity (i.e., God does not lie). If it is against God's nature to be a
deceitful evil genius, then I can infer that what I, His creature, perceive as
"clear and distinct" with my mind or what is told me by God-given
"common sense" (what Descartes calls the "teachings of
nature") is true and certain. One of the things that is taught me by my
"common sense" is that the ideas which I have of the material world
come to me from outside myself. Since the Creator God is not a deceiver, we can
infer that such a material world, independent of the thinking self, truly
exists.
The Rationalist
Transformation
When at the end of
Meditation 6, the last of the meditations, Descartes says, "Hence I should
no longer fear that those things that are daily shown me by the senses are
false. On the contrary, the hyperbolic doubts of the last few days ought to be
rejected as ludicrous," one is lead to believe that the created and
uncreated orders, as they stood prior to the employment of the rationalist
doubt, have now been reinforced as they were with the added note of
"mathematical" certainty. This initial impression is deceptive,
however. Coming out from the employment of a universal and radical doubt, the
basic realities, of God, man, and the natural material world have been
transformed. Man has become a thinking thing, a thing that is philosophically
and epistemologically restricted to analyzing its own ideas, the disembodied
modern consciousness floating in the consumerist shopping mall.
The material world that
emerges from this doubt, is not the one which Aristotle and St. Thomas speak
of, a world of quality and fragrance and form, with a movement inculcated in
the "bosom" of every being, directing it towards its own proper end,
with the ultimate end of all things being, in some real way, God Himself.
Descartes files such rational orientation and divinely planned fulfillment away
from all beings. The red rose has become, not a thing to be marveled at, but a
thing to be measured. The only aspect of nature that is taken seriously by
modern science and education is that aspect of nature that can be quantified
and measured. The ghost of human consciousness floats from mall to machine.
It is the reality of God,
however, which suffers the most abuse from Descartes's rationalist method, even
though it seems as if no one in the history of philosophy has "used"
God more extensively than does Descartes. Now, however, God is reduced to a
"fruitful" idea that helps Descartes achieve the practical scientific
results that he so much wants. It will not be too long before philosophers,
following the path that Descartes laid out, will being treating God as an idea
emerging from human consciousness alone, whose time is up! When Nietzsche makes
the famous statement, echoing Hegel, that "God is dead," he is simply
stating that the "idea" of God has slipped out, for good, of the
consciousness of European Man. The God known by the plenitude of His creation,
always studiously avoided by Descartes's a priori mind, is thus banished
and, therefore, hidden from the inquiring man's reflective eye.
Descartes and Education
When considering the
fallout from the Rationalist "razing" of Scholastic philosophy in so
much of the Christian world, more must be considered than merely the obvious
subjectivism and encroaching relativism that has been seen for the past 350
years. It was the point in which Descartes agreed with the Skeptics of his
time, their rejection of the reliability of sensation as a foundation for
understanding, which should concern us most and indicate the path of
restoration ahead. Now, in the contemporary process of education, the young are
being presented with mathematical reconstructions of the world around them.
Having been reduced to its quantitative aspects, at least for the "hard
sciences," the world of common human experience is ignored while
reconstructed "models" of reality are presented to the young mind.
Since God, the real God and not the "idea" of God, of course, did not
make man to interact, both physically and psychologically, with Cartesian
models of things, there will necessarily be, and we might even say that it is a
healthy sign of nature "revolting," a lack of interest in such
mathematical and scientific models on the part of the great majority of
students, and a mere mechanical, "problem solving" habit on the part
of those who are "interested." Nothing resonates; nothing follows the
grain of the created human embodied psyche. Is it surprising then that much of
the "work" which is done in the mathematically oriented disciplines
has no long lasting impact on the emerging self-understanding of contemporary
youth? To build bombs, it is useful; to build boys, it is not.
To strike at Modernism,
we must plunge into the very heart of the matter. If man is to gain both his
theological, philosophical, political, and psychological balance, he must
recover that hardy realm which Descartes banished. To take seriously St.
Thomas's teaching that all knowledge begins with sensation, that all our
knowledge concerning the existence of real things depends first on our seeing,
touching, tasting, smelling, and feeling them, such would be the beginning of a
return to sanity. For the great Thomistic tradition, the soft, bitter, pungent,
melodious aspects of the natural world provide us with both a knowledge of the
existence and the nature of things, along with stepping-stones from creatures
to Creator. Let the myriads of Cartesian Men have their "mastery of
nature." For us, it is hard to love the gas station that stands on the
spot where the lilies once grew.
Thank you, Dr. Chojnowski, for reproducing your article here, otherwise I wouldn't have noticed it. It makes for a pretty intense read.
ReplyDeleteReaders who want to see the footnotes can click on their respective number to be taken to the Angelus Online site containing the entire article, the notes to which are preceded by the following bio which is likewise truncated above:
Dr. Peter E. Chojnowski has an undergraduate degree in Political Science and another in Philosophy from Christendom College. He also received his Master's Degree and doctorate in Philosophy from Fordham University. He and his wife, Kathleen, are the parents of five children. He teaches for the Society of Saint Pius X at Immaculate Conception Academy, Post Falls, ID.